In
his book Theory As History (Brill
Academic Publishers, 2010), Jairus Banaji makes the claim that we should not
reduce a particular mode of production to one specific form of exploitation,
such as the capitalist mode to wage labour. ‘Relations of production are simply
not reducible to forms of exploitation, both because modes of production
embrace a wider range of relationships than those in their immediate process of
production and because the deployment of labour, the organisation and control
of the labour-process, “correlates” with historical relations of production in
complex ways’ (Banaji 2010, 41).
Instead, Banaji introduces the notion of commercial or merchant capitalism from
at least the 13th century onwards, based on the availability of
finance and functioning institutions of long-distance trade, i.e. a ‘capitalism
that invested widely in a range of economic sectors beyond commerce in its
narrower definition’ (Banaji
2018). What this, however, overlooks is the centrality of wage labour in the
capitalist mode of production and Marx’s insistence on exploitation taking
place in the ‘hidden abode of production’ (see Modes
of Production and Forms of Exploitation).
Distinguishing
between a capitalist social formation and a capitalist mode of production, in
this guest post Tony Burns provides
a way of how we can retain the focus on the centrality of wage labour for
capitalism, without overlooking the possibility of several forms of
exploitation co-existing at the same time.
Tony Burns: It
is not correct that for Marx capitalism might be associated with more than one
form of exploitation, or with different mechanisms for extracting the surplus
product. This is not accurate. Here we need to distinguish between capitalism
as a mode of production and capitalism as a social formation, i.e. a capitalist
society containing more than one mode of production.
In
a capitalist social formation there may be more than one mode of production
present. However, one of these, the capitalist mode, is dominant. In a
pre-capitalist social formation, the capitalist mode of production might be
present, but is not dominant.
Marx
discusses the capitalist mode of production in Capital Volume 1. He associates this with production of commodities
by wage-labour for a market. Here the surplus product is extracted or siphoned
off from the direct producer by the wages and profits system. As Kayhan rightly
said (in the bar), Marx states that it is only the direct producer who adds
value and is the source of surplus value. This is the one and only form of
exploitation that Marx associates with the capitalist mode of production. In
other modes of production the mechanism of surplus extraction takes a different
form. E.g. in the feudal mode of production it takes the direct form of
labour-service.
I
have looked again at the well-known passage from Capital, Volume III, where Marx discusses this issue and append it
below:
‘[1056] If we
consider ground-rent in its simplest form, that of labour rent [1057] where the direct producer,
using instruments of labour (plough, cattle, etc.) which actually or legally
belong to him, cultivates soil actually owned by him during part of the week,
and works during the remaining days upon the estate of the feudal lord without
any compensation from the feudal lord, the situation here is still quite clear,
for in this case rent and surplus-value are identical. Rent, not profit, is the
form here through which unpaid surplus-labour expresses itself.
To what extent the
labourer (a self-sustaining serf) can secure in this case a surplus above his
indispensable necessities of life, i.e., a surplus above that which we would
call wages under the capitalist mode of production, depends, other
circumstances remaining unchanged, upon the proportion in which his labour-time
is divided into labour-time for himself and enforced labour-time for his feudal
lord. This surplus above the indispensable requirements of life, the germ of
what appears as profit under the capitalist mode of production, is therefore
wholly determined by the amount of ground-rent, which in this case is not only
directly unpaid surplus-labour, but also appears as such.
[1059] The
specific economic form, in which unpaid surplus-labour is pumped out of direct
producers, determines the relationship of rulers and ruled, as it grows
directly out of production itself and, in turn, reacts upon it as a determining
element. Upon this, however, is founded the entire formation of the economic
community which grows up out of the production relations themselves, thereby simultaneously
its specific political form….
Rent is here the
primeval form of surplus-labour and coincides with it. But this identity of
surplus-value with unpaid labour of others need not be analysed here because it
still exists in its [1060] visible, palpable form, since the labour of the
direct producer for himself is still separated in space and time from his
labour for the landlord and the latter appears directly in the brutal form of
enforced labour for a third person.’
Marx
makes it clear here that the capitalist mode of production and the feudal mode
of production do have certain things in common, which is not surprising as they
are both associated with the idea of a class-divided society. For example, they
both involve surplus labour and the extraction, siphoning off or pumping out of
a surplus product from the direct producer, who is either a
proletarian/wage-worker or a peasant. However, there are also significant
differences between them, because the mechanism of extraction of this surplus
product relies on the wage-system in the one case, whereas in the other it does
not. Marx does not argue that the capitalist mode of production itself contains
different mechanisms of surplus extraction, or different forms of exploitation.
On
the other hand, if we are talking about a capitalist social formation, or a
capitalist society which contains other modes of production in addition to the
dominant capitalist mode, then it would be correct to say that more than one
form of exploitation is present. Strictly speaking, therefore, to say that for
Marx capitalism might be associated with more than one form of exploitation would
only be correct if by ‘capitalism’ we mean a capitalist social formation, i.e.
a ‘capitalist society.’ It would not be correct if by ‘capitalism’ is meant the
capitalist mode of production.
Dr. Tony Burns is Associate Professor in the School of Politics and International Relations at Nottingham University, UK. His writings on Marx include the following:
Marx, The Labour Theory of Value and the Transformation Problem,’ Capital & Class, 41, 1 (2017), pp. 1-18.
Dr. Tony Burns is Associate Professor in the School of Politics and International Relations at Nottingham University, UK. His writings on Marx include the following:
‘Marx and
Scientific Method: A Non-Metaphysical View,’ in Tony Burns & Ian Fraser
eds., The Hegel-Marx Connection (London:
Macmillan, 2000), pp. 79-104.
‘Review
of Paul Blackledge, Reflections on the
Marxist Theory of History,’ Capital
& Class, 98 (2009), pp. 149-54.
‘Capitalism,
Modernity and the Nation State: A Critique of Hannes Lacher,’ Capital & Class, 101 (2010), pp.
235-55.
Interpreting and Appropriating Texts in
the History of Political Thought: Quentin Skinner and Poststructuralism,’ Contemporary Political Theory, 10, 3
(2011), pp. 313-31.
Marx, The Labour Theory of Value and the Transformation Problem,’ Capital & Class, 41, 1 (2017), pp. 1-18.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Comments welcome!